|

"Beyond
Belief." Oil on canvas by Alicia Mroz.
The No-Belief Belief System
Aug 05, 2010
I believe in not believing.
I try not to believe anything, which
is not the same as believing
nothing. Even though nothing is not
something, believing in nothing is
still believing, and I try not to do
that.People seldom ask me
what I mean by "believe." They argue
that I must believe something, or
they smile and roll up their eyes. I
don't take offense: On alternate
days, I smile and roll my eyes at
myself, too. I do have an excuse for
my confusion.
Before I can say what I mean by
"believe," I have to say something
about what I mean by "mean."
Consider the ideas of heads and
tails. They stand in opposition to
each other. You can't have one if
you have the other. It's either/or.
It's yes/no. It's good/bad.
Let's put all these heads and tails
in a small room with a hole in its
ceiling. Now imagine a conceptual
ladder. It runs through the hole in
the ceiling. Climb the ladder. Stick
your head out the hole. Look around.
You're in a larger room, one that
completely encloses the
heads-and-tails room. This larger
room is full of ideas of coins. Each
coin has a head and a tail on
obverse and reverse sides, but the
coin is a whole. The head and the
tail are merely parts that are
thought of as opposites, along with
other parts (the edge, the metal,
the shape) that aren't thought of as
opposites. So what were opposites in
the room below are unities in the
room above. You've just discovered a
nested hierarchy of ideas.
Ideas other than opposites can also
nest into hierarchies. In logic, one
such hierarchy is the distinction
between an object language and a
metalanguage. The object language is
the one in which you formulate
statements. The metalanguage is the
one in which you talk about the
object language. In the metalanguage,
you don't care about the content of
statements. You pay attention
instead to how the statements
interact.
The metalanguage is a higher or more
inclusive or more abstract level of
meaning than the object language.
The same term may be used in both
languages, but in the object
language it refers to its content
and in the metalanguage it refers to
its function in the object language.
For example, in the first sentence
in this essay I first use "believe"
in a metalanguage mode: how I choose
to evaluate the overall processes of
the evaluation of particular
theories. Then I use it ("not
believing") in an object language
mode: how I evaluate particular
theories.
Now I can answer the first question:
What do I mean by "believe"? In the
object language mode, I mean placing
greater confidence in a particular
theory than is warranted by the
facts and by the nature of
cognition. Notice there can be a
complimentary definition:
"Disbelief" is the placing of less
confidence than is warranted. To
place the proper level of confidence
in a theory, i.e., to avoid both
belief and disbelief, all I need do
is evaluate the facts and the
operation of cognition. Theories can
then be given an index of
confidence, and the one with the
highest number can be judged most
credible.
Unfortunately, I immediately run
into an insoluble problem. Facts are
polymorphic and cognition is
creative. Facts take on different
meanings depending on the theory in
which they're used. Cognition
selects and applies different
pigments of facts to paint different
pictures of reality. So what's
warranted cannot be calculated.
That's not to say reason can't come
up with good excuses for believing
or disbelieving an idea. Reason is
an abject slave: When Desire gives a
command, Reason obeys.
So if warrants are indeterminate,
why bother with belief at all? You
can skirt the issue of confidence
and still use an idea as a working
hypothesis. You can still test the
idea and experiment with it and
develop its logical implications.
What's left after belief is
abandoned is a provisional idea
that's subject to critical
evaluation and testing: In other
words, science.
If this is the cup with which we
measure science, the most notable
aspect is the great quantity that
spills over the edge. Theories,
speculations, idle thoughts,
surmises are barely articulated
before someone judges them by the
criterion of "credibility." Because
you can't put numbers on
"credibility," the criterion
deflates to mere "familiarity."
Peer-reviewed papers are rejected
because they're not credible, but
the only apparent objection is that
they disagree with a currently
accepted theory.
A more sophisticated reaction to
innovation is the listing of
evidence. The idea is that the
theory with the longest list is
best. New theories are at a
disadvantage because they haven't
been around as long to collect as
much evidence. The accumulation of
evidence can never "prove" a theory.
Nothing can guarantee that some new
theory won't explain more things
better.
If credibility can't be calculated
and confirmation can't be counted
on, how are we to know if our
knowledge is true? I'd make a
distinction between true and
truthful: "True" is an exact
representation of some hypothetical
rock-solid reality; "truthful" is a
correspondence with selected parts
of a reality that includes and is
interactive with the knower. What
"truthful" lacks in confidence is
more than made up for in
adaptability to a dynamic and
hierarchical reality. "True" is
dogmatic, "truthful" is critical.
Karl Popper developed this idea of
criticism as the criterion of
demarcation between science and all
the other cognitive efforts to
understand our world. Theology,
metaphysics, pseudo-science, even
politics can be just as meaningful
as science. They can be beneficial
or detrimental, just as can science.
There's a reason dogmatic theology
is called dogmatic: The fundamental
tenets of faith are not subject to
critical evaluation. Now there's a
good and useful place for dogmatism,
too. What sets science apart, what
distinguishes it, is the
encouragement of criticism, even of
fundamentals.
This is why science moves and the
others stand fast. This is why
science progresses and the others
preach. This doesn't mean we should
abolish the others. Most ideas arise
in pseudo-science or metaphysics or
theology. They become scientific
when they're criticized and tested.
They can become metaphysical or
pseudoscientific again if the
criticism and testing stop.
Belief is an anchor that prevents
the winds of criticism from blowing
the ship of curiosity into new
cognitive waters. Belief turns
science into the pseudo-religion of
scientism, which then tries to wrest
from established religions the
sacerdotal claim to revelation of
divine truth. Criticism, especially
of fundamentals, will be the first
sacrificial offering slaughtered on
the new altar.
Science is not all of life, and
curiosity is not the only reason for
living, but they are an important
part. As long as this limitation is
respected, belief can be excised
from science, and science can
continue to discover new worlds.
Mel Acheson
|
|
|
|
|
YouTube video, first glimpses of Episode Two in the "Symbols of an Alien Sky"
series.
|
|
|
|
Three ebooks in the Universe Electric series are
now available. Consistently
praised for easily understandable text and exquisite graphics.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|